Hack
the Abstraction—and Again
Arendt situates the polemic within the etymological
framework noting the first mention of the word revolution on July 14, 1789.
Allegedly, when Louis XVI commenting on the occupation of the Bastille called it
revolt, it was suggested to him by Liancourt that a more accurate term would be
revolution (On Revolution 38).
According to Arendt’s commentaries, up to that moment, the meaning of the word
revolution was known solely from the realm of astronomy. Particularly, it denoted
cyclical movements of heavenly bodies. The symbolic of orbits that Liancourt could
have implied in his remark might concern the historical fact disclosing the corruption
of revolutionary freshness after the first phase characterized by unprecedented
social shifts. In the aftermath of those tectonic reconfigurations, what is
nowadays known as revolution started its downfall toward the climax of a
distorted version of the initial vision. In other words, the trope might
highlight that the events were revolving around the axis of revolt only to end
up at the stage at which the state of affairs was not very different from what
it was like at the very starting point, i.e., that the upheaval had gone full
circle (only, the ruling elites—oppressive at that— were now composed of the
subjects who once had fought against inhumanely brutal social conditions in the
monarchy).
Yet, one can’t help but wonder how Liancourt could
foresee the dynamics in question. Hence, one suspects that he might have had a
different meaning in mind when he suggested a more accurate term for the
turmoil. If so, what could it be? What does Liancourt talk about when he talks
about revolution? One would like to know. From a contemporary point of view,
what happened in France in 1789 hardly fits into the definition of revolution
as the struggle for power on behalf of the proletariat. The notion of a working
classes demographic in France in 1789 is highly questionable. So is it with
regard to the situation in America prior to that. But then, how capitalist was
the Tsarist Russia in 1917, let alone in 1905? One would like to know.
When was revolution? According to some
interpretations of historical records, it has happened more than once at
different points in history at various locations. Yet, what those
interpretations fail to see is a difference between the actual bloodsheds and what
revolution is and should/can be. Scrutinizing Machiavelli’s strategy, Arendt
demystifies erratic equations between certain violence inclined and/or violence
soaked historical phenomena on the one hand and, on the other, revolution:”his
insistence on the role of violence in politics was due not so much to his
so-called realistic insight into human nature as to his futile hope that he
could find some quality in certain men to match the qualities we associate with
the divine” (On Revolution 29).
Clearly, Arendt is in uncompromising disagreement with delusional demigodliness:
We shall see later that
this latter part of the task of revolution, to find a new absolute to replace
the absolute of divine power, is insoluble because power under condition of
human plurality can never amount to omnipotence, and laws residing on human
power can never be absolute. (On
Revolution 29)
Just as she is critical of violence pertinent to
conduct based on a deceitful idea of human omnipotence, so does Arendt object
to senselessness characterizing radical approaches to dedication to a cause--destructiveness partly
sacrificial, partly directed toward the other. There are two major pillars of
Arendt’s thought that safeguard her stance against such mindless strategies and
tactics. First and foremost, it is the idea that investment in freedom,
inherent in revolution, is also the main generator of revolutionary energies.
The fervor engendered by virtue of such affinity is incompatible with (self)-destructiveness.
Choosing death can by no means be part of wholesome sociopolitical reasoning,
save in a symbolic sense such as in the idea of death to self. This maneuver,
essentially anchored in humbleness, ensures vital responses in the individual
and the communal realms. It is in a reciprocally supportive relationship with
the predilection to create, rather than to destroy:”the revolutionary spirit,
that is the eagerness to liberate and
to build a new house where freedom can dwell, is unprecedented and unequalled
in all prior history” (On Revolution 25). Destruction and aggression are in a mutually fueling
relationship with dominance driven socioscape. A devotee to unorthodox
understanding of power relations, Arendt states the futility of the attempts to
revolutionize otherwise:
In the contest that
divides the world today and in which so much is at stake, those will probably
win who understand revolution, while those who still put their faith in power
politics in the traditional sense of the term and, therefore, in war as the
last resort of all foreign policy may well discover in a not too distant future
that they have become masters in a rather useless and obsolete trade. (On Revolution 8)
It seems that the word revolution entered the socio-historical
dialogue in a slightly capricious fashion. It continued in a no less tainted
manner. Thus, to hack it back to the realm where one reckons it belongs will
require undoing at least twofold bastardization in discourse and the
extralinguistic alike.
Like turntablist poetics, the remix : reemergence of
the human face from blurry amalgamation--out of cacophony, and through subtonic
hi-fi solidarity in peaceful/peaceable resistance.
Eathix
off politix, a.k.a., happiness
Scrutinizing the pathways of revolutionary
unfolding, Arendt is concerned with hindsight as a vehicle of reading into
historical records paradigms that color words and apprehension with a shade of
mystique. Specifically, nowadays, it is impossible to think the concept of
revolution disregarding marxian context. Arendt points to the weird occasion of
the intersection between economy / economics and politics in Marx’s political
economy. “Political economy” of the period ensuing his time has seen
civilization deeply entrenched in a nomadic haze of dislocated categories
crippling the socioscape to the point of an image distorted beyond (self)recognition.
She detects the slippery slope, basically, featured
in materialist dialectics heavily relying on hegelian legacy. More precisely,
it is the emphasis on poverty as the cause of violence, instead of vice versa,
that has enabled the development of the sociopolitical irrevocably fixated on
materialist aspects. Thus, in retrospect, the French Revolution was mainly
carried out on the bodily level. Put differently, in her opinion, Robespierre
saw the number of participants gathered together around the common cause as the
force leading toward the changes aspired by the revolutionaries: because of
poverty, they were oppressed; hence they rebelled against it.
What in such a scenario becomes crudely severed to
the point of invisibility is the ideological realm. The very fact that it is so
magically marginalized becomes invisible, as well. Having undergone both
discursive and extralinguistic manipulation, the social, essentially, appears
as the economic under the disguise of the political. In the context of the
French Revolution, Arendt observes:”Meanwhile, the revolution has changed its
direction; it aimed no longer at freedom, the goal of the revolution had become
the happiness of the people” (On
Revolution 51). Likewise, within the framework of the October Revolution,
she demarcates:”Not freedom but abundance became now the aim of revolution” (On Revolution 54).
A marxist perspective, negotiating between hegelian
chemistry of reversibility and the positivist
(nonpopperian) paradigm, resulted in a somewhat deterministic vocabulary
that as much as it aimed to empower, so did it limit possibilities for the
dispossessed. One can’t help but suspect that insistence on the economic focus
of socio-political dynamics may be a highly oppressive mechanism of control.
Once the regime against which the uprising was directed is overthrown and new
“political” elites rise to power, the “revolutionaries”-turned-rulers find
economic vocabulary to be an extremely efficient manipulative—potentially
sacrificial/scapegoating--means. Once people become deprived of the awareness
of the significance and role of ideology, blind spots are created and room for
a contestation of critical thinking is ensured through apparatuses of
conventional power politics, to borrow Arendt’s wording.
She identifies the detail that, to her mind,
distinguishes the American Revolution from the French Revolution in terms of
the perception of individuality and power. Namely, while the French Revolution
centered the fuelling motivation, that Arendt defines in terms of passion of
compassion, around the inflated image of revolutionary leaders, the
revolutionary predecessors anchored their liberation in God, not men. Yet, one
can’t help but wonder if such a focus may exclude passion of compassion for
fellow humans. One would like to know.
The logic of peaceful/peaceable resistance in the
service of the remix creates a platform for dialogue between and among
distinct, yet coexisting and possibly compatible, spheres. The response against
social ills as described in and inferred from Arendt’s theory, from a
contemporary point of view resonates with Baudrillard’s remark from The Vital Illusion (2000):
Through the media, it is the masses who manipulate those in power
(or those who believe themselves to be). It is when the political powers think
they have the masses where they want them that the masses impose their
clandestine strategy of neutralization, of destabilization of a power that has
become paraplegic. (53)
All
the hindsight aiming to destabilize historical records certainly does not
diminish the significance of Marx’s teaching based on profound investment in
revolution. Nor does it prevent one from enduring in peaceful/peaceable
resistance: persevering in disambiguating kaleidoscopically reversed image of
socio-political categories and realities. Neither elitist nor populist is
revolutionary endurance in cultivating the capacity to discern and sustain the
distinction between individualism and individuality, between uniformity and
unity.
No comments:
Post a Comment