Undoing Equations : Solidarity beyond Pain
Several
centuries ago, however, there were no media to channel agency. And yet, there
were certainly means of oppressive control akin to manipulative strategies
known to those who nowadays inhabit the world. The core of social ills the
planet confronts at the moment includes ramifications of a distorted ideology
Arendt delineates investigating the Rousseau – Robespierre nexus. Namely,
Rousseau’s thought elevates passion over, to his mind, detrimental rule of
reason. That it found fertile soil in creative circles thirsting to establish
poetry as a privileged social vocabulary, while reconfiguring vocabulary of
classicism, is not central to this study, but is worth mentioning. Of greater
significance is the way such social reconfigurations entailed mixed up perception
and practice of the ethical, social, political, and economic spheres. More
precisely, accentuating poverty, i.e., economic factors, and advocating passion
over reason engendered some mistaken equations.
Not
only does such reductionist thinking cripple the perception and experience of
ethical categories and morality (the rich are by default bad, and being poor is
by definition either stigmatized or glorified), but it also enables crude
violation of the distinction between the public and the private, a major
consequence of which has been increasing intrusion of the state in the private
realm and overregulation of the life of an individual. The roots of such
socioscape can be tracked via Arendt’s insights into Robespierre’s politics
based on (or, indeed, equated with) the social, where the question of poverty
was considered not as a problem of a person struggling to sustain bare
existence, but rather as the phenomenon pertinent to a particular social
stratum (class? mass?).
Perversion
of the so called politics that under the disguise of humaneness perpetuates
sociopolitical dynamics stemming from and manifested in interest, greed,
materialist wealth based mindedness, sheer utility, hostility, to name but a
few characteristics that have been spelling out currency of social exchange
since major historical occurrences enabled repositioning of power mainly
incarnated in rulers. Paradoxically, the same politics was instrumental in
propagating “selflessness” of the people for the purpose of higher (?) goals,
while masterminding the climate nourishing grandeur of the ruler. Needless to
say, this cleared the way for oppressive regimes ranging from tyranny, via
dictatorship to totalitarianism that Arendt extensively interrogates and
criticizes elsewhere. In that context, she rightly notes the centrality of the
question of hypocrisy and related issues of appearance, surfaces,
superficialities, difference, and sameness.
How
we relate to each other has a crucial role in the sustenance of the communal
generating fruitful exchange free from distraction and noise, and anchored in
humbleness. It calls for revisiting Arendt’s take on the distinction between
pity and solidarity. She remarks that pity is inevitably conditioned by hostile
relationships, i.e., one can only feel pity if somebody is suffering.
Conversely, solidarity is possible in positive circumstances, as well. It is
worth noting that Richard Rorty in Irony,
Contingency, and Solidarity (1989) limits the use – and, indeed,
understanding – of the notion of solidarity to empathy with the suffering of
others, thereby implying that it (solidarity, i.e.) is a connective in
sensitizing to the common ability to feel pain. In contrast, Arendt offers an
angle for thinking humanity both in a communal and individual senses through
the framework that supersedes pity. One can think solidarity beyond pain.
(At Least) Twofold Undoing – Again : Masks of
Dis/integration
There are two ways of approaching the
conundrums Arendt delineates. Neither can expose the origins and / or the cause
of the consequences mainly manifested in ruthless utilitarianism, reckless
competitiveness, and mindless survivalism. Neither can explain exactly how to
articulate an alternative, a counterpoint. Both, however, tackle the problem of
a distorted image of social functioning. Both are critical of a deceitful
belief in the prosperity and wellbeing of the community of humans solely based
on fiscal logic and materialist aspects of the everyday.
Terry Eagleton, for example, illuminates
expropriation of the term norm resulting from a bewildering mix of mutually
conditioned mirroring between discursively engineered cultural categories and
the extralinguistic. In After Theory (2003),
he writes:”The norm now is money; but since money has no principles or identity
of its own, it is no kind of norm at all” (16-17).
Addressing a slightly different angle of the, basically, same cluster of issues, T.S. Eliot verbalizes the polemic across the class divide, while clearly accentuating the role tradition and religion have in his social vocabulary. It is in The Idea of a Christian Society (1940) where he extensively considers the question of living within the human community. Thus, part of the social imagination can be perceived via the following excerpt:
And the tendency of unlimited industrialism is
to create bodies of men and women--of all classes--detached from tradition,
alienated from religion, and susceptible to mass suggestion: in other words, a
mob. And a mob will be no less a mob if it is well fed, well clothed, and well
disciplined. (19)
Neither rigid nor lawless, neither ossifyingly
reactionary-conservative nor repudiating tradition is the basis for
reconfiguring socioscape in the light of the abovementioned thinkers. Hannah
Arendt is obviously in accord with the critique of reductionist understanding
of humans both as individuals and participants in the life of the society. She
develops a discussion tracking the phenomena to the times of Robespierre. The
crux of the debate is the concept of hypocrisy and the way it was dealt with
during the days of the French Revolution. Namely, there is something about
hypocrisy and the mission the revolutionaries found themselves on that,
elucidated through the lens of Arendt’s theory, opens up the avenue for rethinking
society, politics, individuality, and language with an awareness of ambiguity
and its, paradoxically, alleviating effect.
Arendt puts emphasis on the hypocrisy hunt the rebels were on while
overthrowing the regime of utter corruption. The monarchy turned out to be the
very incarnate of hypocrisy, but, as Arendt demonstrates, no less erratic was
an attempt to presume one’s own self to be entirely hypocrisy free. It implies
a total absence of the sense of humbleness. In addition, situated--as Arendt
does it in those genealogical excavations--within the etymological unfolding,
the questions meet some of the most significant philosophical themes such as
the appearance-being nexus. Arendt indicates salient instances of diverse
approaches to the issue. The ancient Greeks, Socrates in particular, held
appearances to be closely related to the perception of one’s identity. By
contrast, supposedly “in the tradition of Christian thought” (On Revolution 91), from Machiavelli’s point of view, appearances are precisely the opposite
of who one is.
Arendt invokes the word persona
that in Latin “signified the mask ancient actors used to wear in a play” (On Revolution 97). She draws a parallel showing the significance
of “roles” in social context assigned to an individual that one assumes,
thereby taking part in the life of the community and reanimating an aspect of
self constitutive of some distinctive features. Specifically, those might be
socially constructed and designated descriptions of self, but they are also
hugely important, since they don’t have to be impositions, but rather liberating
channels of social dynamics that relieve one of a description and perception
exclusively in biological terms. It is in tune with instincts stemming from the
aspects of the human being that exceed the sheer realm of the bodily. It surely
offers a possibility of religiosity free religion. As such, it is particularly
informative of the understanding of sin, law, deeds, mercy, forgiveness, to
name but a few critical categories many religions regard as essential.
Such a counter-babylonian, anti-mammonesque stand simultaneously
provides a perspective from which discursively conditioned categories are acknowledged
as versatile, yet not indiscriminately multifarious, unleashed proliferation of
narratively manipulated realities. From that angle, it seems that,
paradoxically, as Arendt sees it, hypocrisy is the vice of vices. Not only does
“anti-hypocritical hypocrisy” imply an individual’s blindness to one’s fallacy,
but it also entails a complete disregard of one’s inauthenticity, since it is
an attempt at a total eradication of the awareness of falsehood, hence a
person’s disavowal of integrity. Additionally, it is crude violation of
critical thinking and blatant neglect of a critical distance. It is an instance
of extreme, uncritical suspense of disbelief.
No comments:
Post a Comment